arianna Uggèuniversità Vita-Salute San raffaele
REPRESENTATIONALISM AND AMBIGUOUS FIGURES
abstractThe phenomenon of ambiguous figures raises difficulties for the theories of the content of our visual experience that hold that its phenomenal character is identical to its representational content and whol y nonconceptual. This phenomenon seems to show that there can be a difference in the phenomenal character of two visual experiences, without a difference in their representational nonconceptual content. firstly, i shall try to il ustrate that these “representationalist” theories cannot provide a compel ing explanation for the phenomenon of ambiguous figures. Secondly, I will present an account of it grounded on Peacocke’s “dual nonconceptual content” view. The distinction he draws between two levels of nonconceptual content can be used to explain the phenomenon without abandoning the thesis that the phenomenal character of our visual experience is a representational wholly nonconceptual content.keywordsRepresentationalism, ambiguous figures, visual experience, phenomenal character
RePResentatIonaLIsM anD aMBIgUoUs fIgUResarianna UggÉ università Vita-Salute San raffaele 1. The phenomenon of ambiguous figures consists in the fact that a single figure Introduction can ground experiences of, at least, two different and incompatible percepts,
even though the geometrical properties of the figure are not experienced as
changing. In other words, ambiguous figures are those that a subject can see in
two sharply different ways, while being aware of the fact that the shape, size,
texture, etc. of the figure remain constant. Moreover, a subject can “switch”
from seeing the figure in one way to seeing it in another way (this is cal ed
“figure reversal” or “gestalt switch”). This phenomenon poses difficulties for the
theorists of the content of visual experience and, in particular, for the advocates
concerning the debate about the content of our visual experience, i hold that
there are good reasons to consider it to be, at least in part, nonconceptual. this
claim is supported by several arguments that underline, in particular, that our
experience is characterized by a wealth of elements and details that cannot
be ful y captured in conceptual terms. nevertheless, the case of ambiguous
figure seems to show that an exhaustive specification of the content of the
corresponding visual experiences must include conceptual constituents. as
Wittgenstein remarks, the phenomenon of ambiguous figures seems to be an
intermediate case between visual experience and thought.1
the main claim of (strong) representationalism – in the versions i am concerned
with: tye (1995) and dretske (1995) – is that the phenomenal character of a
visual experience, i.e., the “what-it-is-likeness” of having it, is identical to,
or completely determined by, its representational content. in addition, it
states that this content is of a nonconceptual kind. yet, the experience of
an ambiguous figure seems to show that there can be a difference in the
phenomenal character of two visual experiences without a difference in their
representational nonconceptual content. in that case, representationalism
confronts the fol owing disjunction: either it renounces its main thesis—the
phenomenal character is not exhaustively representational; or it abandons the
claim that this character is whol y nonconceptual.
I shall outline an account of ambiguous figures, based on Peacocke’s “dual
nonconceptual content” view, that intends to elude the above-mentioned
disjunction. if successful, phenomenal character could be both whol y
representational and nonconceptual and yet there could be a phenomenal
difference between the experiences corresponding to seeing, e.g., the duck/1 See Wittgenstein (1953).
RePResentatIonaLIsM anD aMBIgUoUs fIgUResarianna UggÉ università Vita-Salute San raffaele
Rabbit figure as a Duck or as a Rabbit. In this way, my account intends to
preserve representationalism’s main claim – that phenomenal character is
representational – and nonconceptualism about phenomenal character. 2. i shall try to show that representationalism cannot provide an adequate Ambiguous explanation of the phenomenon of ambiguous figures. I will formulate an Figures and argument whose structure is similar to that of macpherson (2006)2. Representationalism Let us consider the paradigmatic case of the Duck/Rabbit ambiguous figure (F):
On the one hand, the figure F can be seen as a Duck (A) or as a Rabbit (B). Thus,
it seems clear that F is at the origin of two experiences that differ in their
phenomenal character: in one experience a duck appears and in the other a rabbit.
now, recall that, according to representationalism, phenomenal character is a
representational nonconceptual content. thereby, fol owing representationalism,
between the experiences of seeing F as a and seeing F as b there must be a
difference in the nonconceptual representational content.
on the other hand, it seems intuitively clear that, since both a and b are caused
by the same figure F, there must be something in common in the contents of
these experiences. and indeed, the subject of the experience does not notice
any change in the properties of F when she switches from seeing a to seeing b:
the colors, shapes, and textures she experiences appear to be the same in both
cases. thus, it is reasonable to hold that the representational content of both
experiences is identical at the nonconceptual level.3 now, for representationalism
this content is identical to the phenomenal character. thereby, fol owing
representationalism, the experiences of seeing F as a and seeing F as b should
not differ in their phenomenal characters.
in sum, on the one hand, representationalism requires the experience of
2 However, I propose a different analysis of the problem of ambiguous figures and, unlike
macpherson (2006), i consider that Peacocke’s “dual nonconceptual content view” offers the
resources to elaborate a compelling solution. See Uggè (2012).
3 colors, shapes and textures are paradigmatic nonconceptual contents of visual experience.
This kind of contents is the object of the “fineness of grain” argument for the thesis that the
phenomenal character of visual experience is nonconceptual.
RePResentatIonaLIsM anD aMBIgUoUs fIgUResarianna UggÉ università Vita-Salute San raffaele
seeing an a and the experience of seeing a b to differ in the representational
nonconceptual content. on the other hand, it seems that the representational
nonconceptual content is in common in both experiences. hence,
representationalism seems unable to account for the difference in the
phenomenal character of the experiences of seeing F as an a and seeing F as a b,
without abandoning one of its main tenets.
at the conceptual level there is clearly a difference between the experience of a
duck and the experience of a rabbit, since two different concepts are involved.
thus, a possible explanation for the phenomenal difference between these
experiences might be that concepts determine, somehow, their phenomenal
characters. there are two possibilities to account for the relation between
concepts and the content of experiences: first, to claim that concepts enter
into the content of the experience; and second, to claim that concepts are not
constituents of the content of the experience.
The first possibility is not available for the advocates of representationalism.
First, it doesn’t seem to them that the phenomenal character of our visual
experience includes concepts. Several arguments can be mentioned, e.g., the
argument from infants and superior animals, and the argument from the
fineness of grain.4 according to the latter, visual experience represents the
world with a determinacy of detail that is not capturable in purely conceptual
terms. Second, for representationalism the phenomenal character of our
experience is identical to or completely determined by its representational
content. if concepts entered into the phenomenal character we would have a
representational content that has concepts as constituents and thus is (at least
the second possibility is to claim that concepts determine (top-down) the
difference in the phenomenal character between, e.g., seeing the duck/rabbit
figure as a Duck or as a Rabbit while staying outside of the phenomenal contents
themselves. this proposal is problematic for the fol owing reasons. First, it
supposes that there is cognitive penetrability of perception by thought, and this
is a controversial claim. indeed, the advocates of representationalism defend
the cognitive impenetrability thesis according to which “both the phenomenal
character and the intentional content of perceptual states are impermeable to
states of their subjects’ cognitive systems” (voltolini 2011, 1). evidence against
the penetrability of perception by thought comes from the phenomenon of
the persistence of the il usion.5 consider, for instance, the famous case of the 4 See tye (1995).
RePResentatIonaLIsM anD aMBIgUoUs fIgUResarianna UggÉ università Vita-Salute San raffaele
Mül er-Lyer il usion. When we are looking at the figure we see two segments
that appear to us as being of different lengths, but actual y they are of the same
length. now, the fact that we learn that the segments are of the same length
does not change the way they appear. Second, the question remains, for the
representationalist, regarding what is the difference in the representational
nonconceptual content that accounts for the phenomenal difference between
seeing the duck/rabbit as a duck and as a rabbit.
Representationalists can claim that concepts have an influence on the content
of visual experience that does not involve cognitive penetrability. this proposal
is developed by Tye (1995). He holds that the experience of ambiguous figures
might involve concepts. this is clear in the case of the duck/rabbit: in order
for a subject S to see the figure as duck-shaped she has to possess the concept
“duck”. but, according to tye, concepts play a causal role and not a constitutive role in the experience. the concepts cause two experiences with a different
content, but this content can still be nonconceptual. in tye’s words, “one has a
sensory representation whose phenomenal content is then brought under the
given concepts. Stil , the concepts do not enter into the content of the sensory
representations and they are not themselves phenomenal y relevant” (1995,
however, the proposal just mentioned does not seem able to provide a
compel ing explanation of what is the difference in the phenomenal character
of the experiences determined under the concepts “duck” and “rabbit”. First,
note that in the case of the duck/rabbit we do not notice any difference in the
nonconceptual content of our visual experience before and after the occurrence
of the gestalt switch. thus, it seems that the nonconceptual content remains the
same in both cases, either when we perceive the picture as a duck or as a rabbit.
Second, consider the case of the necker cube (n):
This figure differs in an important respect from the case of the Duck/Rabbit,
RePResentatIonaLIsM anD aMBIgUoUs fIgUResarianna UggÉ università Vita-Salute San raffaele
since it involves only one concept (the cube). its ambiguity concerns the two
different orientations that the cube appears to have. thus, the thesis that
concepts are not part of the content of our visual experience but, nevertheless,
have an effect on its phenomenal character, seems incapable of explaining the
in particular, two criticisms have been moved to tye’s account. according to
“the main problem with this way of arguing is that it is strikingly ad hoc. once one accepts that concepts are required to have a given visual
experience, it is hard to see what could decide between a causal and a
constitutive view [. .] if concepts are required, even if only causal y, to
have visual experiences with given contents, then we wouldn’t be able
to ascribe content to creatures that lack them, and we wouldn’t be in a
position to give a story of how we acquire concepts.” (2011, 312)
in addition, voltolini remarks that tye’s account seems unable to avoid cognitive
penetrability, even though he holds that concepts have a causal and not a
constitutive role. according to him, the fact that the change in the phenomenal
character is conceptual y driven is sufficient to undermine the cognitive
impenetrability thesis, which states that both the phenomenal character
and the intentional content of experience are not permeable by the subject’s
if what we have said so far is on the right track, the legitimate conclusion to
draw is that representationalism seems unable to provide a compel ing account
of the phenomenon of ambiguous figures. In the next section I shall argue that
Peacocke’s (1992) distinction between two levels of nonconceptual content can
be used to ground a compel ing explanation of this phenomenon, without aban-
doning the thesis that the phenomenal character of our visual experience is a
representational whol y nonconceptual content.
3. Firstly, I shall briefly introduce Peacocke’s “dual nonconceptual content” view. Peacocke's "Dual Secondly, I shall discuss the phenomenon of ambiguous figures in the light of Nonconceptual Peacocke’s distinction between two levels of nonconceptual content.7 Content" and the according to Peacocke, our visual experience has a representational content, Phenomenon of 6 See macpherson (2012) and voltolini (2011). i’m indebted to alberto voltolini for this Ambiguous Figures remark.
7 even though Peacocke (1992) does not develop his theory of a “dual nonconceptual content”
view to account for the cases of the Duck/Rabbit and the Necker Cube ambiguous figures, I will
try to show that it can be used for this purpose.
RePResentatIonaLIsM anD aMBIgUoUs fIgUResarianna UggÉ università Vita-Salute San raffaele
since it represents the world as being a certain way. now, this content includes
both conceptual and nonconceptual constituents. in particular, it includes
two kinds of representational nonconceptual contents that he labels “scenario
content” and “protopropositional content”. a “scenario” is considered to be
a “spatial type”, characterized by a way of filling out the space around the
perceiver, consistent with the veridicality of the perceiver’s experience. in
order to specify a spatial type we have to fix an origin and some axes. These
elements are not grounded in specific places or directions in the world, since
a type can be instantiated at different places, but they are relative to the
perceiver who is always present regardless the location at which a type is
instantiated.8 a “protopropositional content” is a nonconceptual content that
has a different structure than that of the scenario content. Protopropositional
content includes individuals, properties, andrelations. For instance, some of
the properties or relations represented are: “parallel to”, “curved”, “square”,
“equidistant from”. It is belief-like (it has a mind-to-world direction of fit),
and is called “protopropositional” since it has a subject-predicate form where
the individuals are the subjects and the properties or relations the predicate.
now, this content is not uniquely determined by the scenario: two experiences
could have the same scenario but a different protopropositional content.
Peacocke remarks that it is precisely on the basis of this distinction, at the
level of nonconceptual content, that is possible to ground our experiential
in short, Peacocke argues that our experience has three layers of content:
scenario content (nonconceptual); protopropositional content (nonconceptual);
now, let us discuss the cases of the duck/rabbit and the necker cube. i will try
to show that the distinction between two nonconceptual levels of content can
be used to account for the ambiguity of these figures.
This figure (F) can be seen either as a Duck (A) or as a Rabbit (B). However,
a subject that undergoes both experiences is aware of being perceiving
the same figure, and the corresponding gestalt switch does not imply any
change in its shape, color or texture. this invariance can be accounted for
by claiming that there is no difference at the level of the scenario content
between seeing F as an a or as a b. in both cases, the space around the
perceiver is filled in the same way. 8If we assign a time to a scenario and fix real directions and places in the world for the origin and
axes, we have what Peacocke labels a “positioned scenario”.
RePResentatIonaLIsM anD aMBIgUoUs fIgUResarianna UggÉ università Vita-Salute San raffaele
Now, when a subject sees F as an A, the left part of the figure represents the
beak of a duck, the right side its head, and the eye is experienced as pointing
to the left. by contrast, when she sees F as a b, the left part represents
the ears of a rabbit, the right side its snout, and the eye is experienced as
pointing to the right. these differences can be captured, at least partially, at
the protopropositional level; they concern relations between different parts
hence, if the phenomenal character is constituted by Peacocke’s two types of
nonconceptual content, it is possible to account for what is in common, and for
what differs, in the experiences of F as an a and as a b.
Certainly, different concepts are involved when the figure is seen as a A and as
b. but these concepts do not need to be taken as constituents of the phenomenal
character of the experience. in fact, Peacocke’s conceptual level of content can
be taken to be outside a visual experience’s phenomenal character. there can
be top-down effects from concepts to the protopropositional level of content,
and bottom-up effects in the inverse direction. Somehow, when the image is
subsumed under the concept “duck” some relations among the parts of the
figure are represented, and these relations differ from the ones that are likewise
represented when it is subsumed under the concept “rabbit”. indeed, according
to Peacocke’s theory, the different levels of content are not autonomous and
there are both top-down and bottom-up effects9.
This two-dimensional figure (F) represents the flat projection of a three-
dimensional cube. The figure can be seen either as a three-dimensional cube
oriented downward (a) or as a three-dimensional cube oriented upward (b).
Since a subject who experiences F as an a or as a b is aware of perceiving the
same figure, and its geometrical properties are not experienced as changing
after a gestalt switch, we can say—fol owing Peacocke’s distinctions—that these
experiences have the same scenario content. yet, the experiences of an a and
of a b differ in the relations being represented as holding between the faces
and the edges of the cube. If we look at the figure on the left, the front-face of
the cube is seen in the front plane and gives rise to the a percept whereas if
we look at the figure on the right, the front-face of the cube is seen in the back
plane and thus gives rise to the b percept. it is possible to account for these
differences by claiming that the experiences of F as an a and as a b differ in
9 in this way, the autonomy thesis - according to which a subject can be in a nonconceptual
state without possessing any concept - is not preserved. in a more recent work Peacocke changed
RePResentatIonaLIsM anD aMBIgUoUs fIgUResarianna UggÉ università Vita-Salute San raffaele
the case of the necker cube supports the claim that the phenomenal differences
between two alternative percepts of an ambiguous figure can be captured
at a nonconceptual level. it is not necessary to involve different concepts as
constituents of the phenomenal character. indeed, the experiences of a necker
cube as an a or as a b – by contrast with the case of the duck/rabbit – do not
frame the figure under different concepts. Both experiences represent a cube.
Differences at the level of the protopropositional content seem sufficient to
account for phenomenal differences between seen F as an a and as a b.
In both the Necker Cube and the Duck/Rabbit figures, concepts certainly have a
top-down effect on the content of experience. in the case of the necker cube, we
can suppose that an infant or an animal that do not possess the concept “cube”
would not be able to see the image as a three-dimensional cube. and similarly,
in the case of the duck/rabbit, if a subject lacks the concepts of “duck” or
“rabbit” she will not be able to see the figure as a Duck and as a Rabbit.
in addition to top-down effects, it seems there are bottom-up ones between
the nonconceptual levels and the conceptual level. it has been argued that
differences in the places where the subject focuses her attention elicit different
concepts . this could be due, at least in part, to the fact that different points of
focus would privilege the representation of different relations among the parts
of the figure. Thereby, protopropositional contents would elicit the exercise
of different concepts.to summarize, the distinction between two layers of
nonconceptual content can account for the existence of:
• a nonconceptual representational content that is in common in the alternative experiences of an ambiguous figure (the scenario content).• a difference in the phenomenal character of the alternative experiences of an ambiguous figure (different protopropositional contents). 4. I have tried to show that ambiguous figures are troublesome for the advocates of Conclusion representationalism. What is particularly problematic in the case of ambiguous
figures is that it proves difficult to provide an explanation of this phenomenon
exclusively in terms of the nonconceptual contents of the corresponding visual
experiences. In fact, when a figure F is seen as an A or as a B, it seems, on the
one hand, that there is a difference in the phenomenal character of these
experiences. but on the other hand, it seems that the qualitative properties of F
such as its shape, size, color, texture, etc. – that are presumably represented in
experience in a nonconceptual way – are shared by these experiences. in other
RePResentatIonaLIsM anD aMBIgUoUs fIgUResarianna UggÉ università Vita-Salute San raffaele
words, the phenomenal difference that there is between seeing F as an a or as a
b does not seem to concern nonconceptual contents.
As a plausible account of the case of ambiguous figures, compatible with the
thesis that the phenomenal character of experience is nonconceptual, i used
Peacocke’s distinction between two levels of nonconceptual content. When
a figure F is seen as an A or as a B, the corresponding experiences share the
same scenario content, but differ in their protopropositional content. the
scenario concerns how the space around the perceiver is fil ed, while the
protopropositional content is the representation of the relations between
Peacocke’s “dual nonconceptual content” view al ows for both top-down and
bottom-up effects between the conceptual and the nonconceptual levels of
content. thus, it seems able to ground a thorough explanation of the case of
ambiguous figures that, as happens with the Duck/Rabbit, require or involve the
exercise of different concepts on the part of the perceiver. in order to have this
explanation we need, first, a detailed account of the relation between concepts
and the phenomenal character. Second, to provide an in-depth clarification of
how the relations between concepts and nonconceptual contents change, in
particular, whenever a gestalt switch occurs. Acknowledgements i would like to thank elisabetta Sacchi, who supervised the master thesis that
this article is based on; alberto voltolini, for his insightful comments on an
earlier version of this article; and reinaldo bernal velásquez, who made a
thorough revision. i am also thankful to the participants at the “Sense and
Sensibility” conference for their observations and comments. in particular, to
barry Smith, roberta de monticel i, and clotilde calabi.
RePResentatIonaLIsM anD aMBIgUoUs fIgUResarianna UggÉ università Vita-Salute San raffaele REFERENCES
dretske, F. (1995), naturalizing the mind, mit Press, cambridge, ma;
Fodor, J. (1983), The modularity of mind, mit Press, cambridge, ma;
macpherson, F. (2006), “ambiguous Figures and the content of experience”, noûs,
macpherson, F. (2012), “cognitive Penetration of colour experience: rethinking
the issue in light of an indirect mechanism”, Philosophy and Phenomenological
orlandi, n. (2011), “ambiguous Figures and representationalism”, Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, vol 10, pp. 307-323;
Peacocke, c. (1992), “Scenarios, concepts and Perception. the content of
experience”. in t. crane (ed.), The Content of experience, cambridge University
Peacocke, c. (2002), “Postscript: the relations between conceptual and
nonconceptual content”. in “nonconceptual content: Kinds, rationales, and
relations” in t. crane (ed.), The Content of experience, cambridge University Press,
Pylyshyn, Z. (2003), Seeing and Visualizing: it’s not What you Think, mit Press,
tye, m. (1995), Ten Problems of Consciousness. cambridge, ma: mit Press.
Uggè, A. (2012), “On the content of visual experience. Ambiguous figures
andrepresentationalism”, master thesis, m.a. in Philosophy of mind and human
being, society and history, University vita-Salute San raffaele (milan);
Voltolini, A. (2011), “How picture Perception Defies Cognitive Impenetrability”.
in a. reboul (ed.), Philosophical papers dedicated to Kevin mul igan, Université de
Wittgenstein, l. (1953), Philosophical investigations. anscombe, g.e.m. rhees, r.
(eds.). anscombe, g.e.m. (trans.) (1953). oxford, blackwel .
“Reinvigorating the Queer Political Imagination” | 845 “Reinvigorating the Queer Political Imagination”: A Roundtable with Ryan Conrad, Yasmin Nair, and Karma Chávez of Against Equality Margot Weiss talked with Ryan Conrad, Yasmin Nair, and Karma Chávez, three members of Against Equality, a queer online archive, publishing, and arts collective that challenges the polit
The term “symbol” is a term quite difficult to define. In ordinary usage, it enjoys a wide variety of meanings. In science it can even be thought to be a base-term in fields as diverse as linguistics, philosophy, theology and mathematics (to mention just a few), but, again, it is questionable whether one may find a single comprehensive pattern to explain and order this diversity. It certai